Like Belgian Chocolate for the Universal Mind. Interpersonal and Media Gossip from an Evolutionary Perspective. (Charlotte De Backer)

 

home list theses contence previous next  

 

PART I

 

THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

 

CHAPTER 1. Conceptualizing and operationalizing gossip

 

“Definitions of gossip will always be complex and controversial.”

(Taylor, 1994: 34)

 

1 Introduction

 

“Most introductory books start with a definition, but I prefer to leave such things to the end, where they can do less damage. Definitions are useful for resolving disputes, but they can easily become intellectual straitjackets, tempting people into the mistaken belief that words have fixed or essential meanings that should be defended against the tide of cultural change and scientific progress.” (Evans, 2001: 147-148)

 

Evans (2001) is correct in saying that definitions fit better at the end of an analytical work. However, before I can analyze ‘gossip’, I still think some conceptualization of my research topic is required. Skipping an introductory conceptualization process of my study would be a methodological fault, or as Wert and Salovey (2004a) recently said:

 

“Although defining and describing gossip is an interesting enterprise in its own right, this difficulty in settling on a definition of gossip may contribute to stymied progress in its study. Indeed, it often seems that the scientific discussion of gossip has bogged down at this first step, that of defining the phenomenon. If empirical researchers are to proceed, they must grapple with this issue of exactly what behavior is being studied when one studies gossip. What ‘counts’ as gossip?” (Wert & Salovey, 2004a: 76)

 

In this chapter I do not want to put forward ‘the’ definition of gossip, but a framework for my analysis on gossip. A more funded and clarifying definition will be the result of my analysis, and be presented later in this dissertation. To argue why a definition is needed both at the beginning and the ending of an introductory book, or study, let me explain with reference to the work of Sapir and Whorf.

 

When thinking about gossip, we use language. When researching gossip and communicating this to others, we use language. It is important to note that in this process it is the language we use that will define how we think about and conduct research on gossip. I refer here to the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis that outlines the relationship between thought and language. Whorf (1956) claims that humans can only think about objects, processes, and so forth that have language linked to them (linguistic determinism). Whorf (1956) further claimed that culture is determined by language (linguistic relativity). How people look at the world is determined by the language that they use.

 

A classical example that is often mentioned when talking about the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis is the amount of words the Eskimo’s use to refer to ‘snow’. However, as Pinker (1994) explains: as much attention has been given to this ‘fact’, it is not true. It is a myth, Eskimos do not have four hundred words for snow, not even two hundred, one hundred or even nine. It is true that experts can come up with a dozen of words, but that is not different from English talking people who as well can come up with multiple words for snow, such as snow, blizzard, avalanche, flurry, hail, etc., therefore:

 

“Where did the myth come from? Not from anyone who has actually studied the Yupik and Inuit-Inupiaq families of polysynthetic languages spoken from Siberia to Greenland. The anthropologist Laura Martin has documented how the story grew like an urban legend, exaggerated with each retelling. In 1911 Boas casually mentioned that Eskimos used four unrelated word roots for snow. Whorf embellished the count to seven and implied that there were more. His article was widely reprinted, then cited in textbooks and popular books on language, which led to successively inflated estimates in other textbooks, articles, and newspaper columns of Amazing Facts.” (Pinker, 1994: 64)

 

Pinker (1994) further criticizes the linguistic relativity for treating other, non-literate cultures as weird compared to our own. Citing Pullum (1991), Pinker (1994) explains that if Eskimos would use various words to refer to snow, this is no different from breeders using various names for breeds, like botanists having names for shapes of leaves and interior decorators having multiple words to describe the subtle shade variations of 'blue'. It is not the words that make us look at things differently, but it is how detailed or focused you look at something that will determine the various names you will use to describe the phenomenon.

 

I mention this debate on the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, because I do agree that how I will first define ‘gossip’ will determine my research on it. I mention the Eskimo-snow hoax, because as my research on gossip progresses in this dissertation, I will claim that various names should be used when looking at gossip as a researcher of this phenomenon. Now, to start off, let me first outline what ‘gossip’ means in a general sense, as a breeder would first explain what a ‘horse’ is in general, before mentioning all the various horse breeds he knows of.

 

To conceptualize and operationalize gossip, I will mainly draw from contributions of the Communication Studies, since as Saunders (1999) claimed that the contribution of Communication Studies to a better understanding of gossip is that they offer definitions of gossip to operationalize the study. Still, before framing gossip within the Communications Model, and outlining the various debates in this discourse, I want to start with an etymological overview. What we call ‘gossip’ today is different from what ‘gossip’ referred to some decades ago. Therefore, I begin with the historical roots of ‘gossip’, and the Dutch variant ‘roddel’. I not only discuss the etymology of the word ‘gossip’ in English, but also focus on the Dutch word ‘roddel’, since a major part of my research will be done in the Dutch speaking part of Belgium.

 

 

2 The words ‘gossip’ and ‘roddel’ in a historical perspective

 

2.1 The word ‘gossip’: from godfather to bad talking mother

 

“Gossip has a bad reputation around town – if not around the world. Among the West African Ashanti, nasty or scandalous gossip about a tribal leader is punished by cutting of the gossiper’s lips.” (Levin & Arluke, 1987: 3)

 

With this awful fact, Levin and Arluke (1987) start to sum up some examples that show that the English word ‘gossip’ clearly has a negative connotation today. In 1936 Henry Lanz published an article in which he compares ‘gossip’ with ‘the devil’:

 

Philologically the word “Devil”, Old English deofol , is derived from Greek diabolos (dia, “through,” and ballein, “‘to cast”), meaning “one who casts words,” “arguer,” “accuser,” “calumniator.” Thus the Devil is originally associated with the “sins of the tongue.” (Lanz, 1936: 492)

 

Lanz then describes how gossip, as the modern evil of our societies is all around, in our daily talk, in written texts, and even in the arts. However, he must admit that he does not know how to ban this evil from our daily lives. At the end of his argument against gossip he concludes:

 

“Strangely enough, the word gossip, be it paradoxically pointed put in conclusion, points in the direction of heaven rather than the Devil.” (Lanz, 1936: 499).

 

This is because, when looking at the etymological history, the word ‘gossip’ hasn’t always had a negative reputation. Up until 1811, according to the Oxford English Dictionary, the noun referred to a mode of conversation in a friendly sense, and not focusing on a person in a bad sense, as it is today (Spacks, 1985). ‘Gossip’ is derived from the old English word godsibb, meaning ‘godparent’ or ‘godfather’. But, as Rysman (1977) explains, the term ‘godfather’ in this context has a broader meaning than just referring to one family member having a close relation with a related child, as today. In times when people lived in more rural settings, all had large social networks of family, friends and acquaintances that all were potential godparents:

 

“In small villages, the god-parents were also neighbors and there must have been considerable talk among them, especially during the idle winter months. The god-parent was not merely a formality; he or she was involved in a pseudo-kin relation with the whole family in a society saturated with kin and pseudo-kin relations. Just as feudalism and chivalry prescribed a set of pseudo-kin relations for the nobility through the institution of vassalage, so the institution of the god-parent relation allowed peasants to develop imaginary familial relations with their peers. For some analytical purpose, one can treat the family and associated god-parents as a single, unitary group.” (Rysman, 1977: 176-177)

 

During the Elizabethan period (16th – 17th centuries) gossip referred to individual relationships, typically masculine, men’s drinking, gathering of male friends in bars, raising the glass. The female variant of gossip pointed to the gathering of family and friends during childbirth. When a woman gave birth, her female family and friends came together to give her support, and that is what gossip was about in the 19th century; meeting with family and friends, socializing with each other:

 

“Jan Steen’s painting dating from 1664 carried the title “Gossiping” and depicted such a domestic scene with the mother lying in bed attended by two women while others surround the kitchen table and heat water by the hearth, gesturing to one another as they engage in conversation.” (Romaine, 1999: 161)

 

By the end of the 19th century the connotation changed, gossip was redefined as ‘idle talk’ and “tattling’, an action that did no longer refer to the social act of gathering, but to a an ordinary, rather negative form of communication (Bergmann, 1993; Brison, 1992; Fox, 2002; Gelles, 1989; Levin & Arluke, 1987; Rosnow & Fine, 1976; Rosnow & Georgoudi, 1985; Rysman, 1977; Spacks, 1985). And remarkably: “The terms for ‘godmother’ in French (commère) and Italian (commare) also took a negative semantic turn, unlike the terms for ‘godfather’.” (Romaine, 1999: 161).

 

Levin and Arluke (1987), Rysman (1977) and Romaine (1999) suppose that during the 19th century men began to fear that their spouses would no longer remain humble. People then were convinced that women should stay at home to cook and take care of their husbands. When they did gathered together with other women what were they doing, and more importantly, what did they discuss? The word gossip not only changed from something good to something bad, but was also no longer a habit of both men and women, but ‘privileged’ to women only; women talk. The fear of men towards their wives became even more apparent when demonstrations were held in England in the 19th century. Pamphlets were distributed to warn people about ‘women talk’, and these conversations were ridiculed and even forbidden:

 

“Gossip poses a threat to the social order because it may give rise to slander and intrigue and expose illicit and secret liaisons. Professions such as midwifery allowed women passage between households, largely free of male control, to exchange mother wit-knowledge of intimate matters such as contraception and abortion. In 17th-century England, broadsheets denounced women’s gossip and its dangerous powers, among them curses and spells.” (Romaine, 1999: 163).

 

The fight against gossip grew in some places. For example, in Texas until the beginning of the 20th century women were no longer allowed to talk to other women outside their own family. Whoever infringed upon the law was punished (Rysman, 1977).

 

To conclude this overview of the English word ‘gossip’, I end by giving the current definition according to Merriam Webster’s Dictionary (www.m-w.com):

 

gos·sip

1 a dialect British: GODPARENT b: COMPANION, CRONY c: a person who habitually reveals personal or sensational facts about others
2 a: rumor or report of an intimate nature b: a chatty talk c: the subject matter of gossip

 

2.2 The history of the word ‘roddel’

 

Compared to the English word ‘gossip’, the Dutch or Flemish variant ‘roddel’ has a more recent history. In Belgium the word first appeared at the end of the nineteenth century, somewhere between 1865 and 1870. When I searched for the meaning of the word ‘roddelen’ in the “Woordenboek der Nederlandsche Taal” of 1924 (Van Der Meulen, 1924) I found a description that does not fit at all in the nowadays use of the word roddel. The word “roddel” back then was used to refer to the rumbling noise of streetcars or the rumbling noise of hungry stomachs:

 

RODDELEN, onz. Zw. Ww. Klanknabootsend ww., in Z-Nederl. gebruikelijk.

Al schuddend, schokkend, hobbelend een dof geluid geven. Verg. Robbelen (I). // Een roddelend rijtuig, SCHUERM. Aan heur roddelen ken ik mijne kar, RUTTEN. De käär roddelt oëp de stiëwäg, TUERL.

Rommelen. Verg. Robbelen (II), 2). // Mijn buik roddelt, SCHEURM. (zie ook TUERL.; RUTTEN).” (Van Der Meulen, 1924: 657).

 

According to van der Sijs (2001) we inherited the word ‘roddel’ from the Yiddish vocabulary, a language that appeared in German ghettos in late Middle Ages, derived from German, Hebrew and Aramese. The language infiltrated the Dutch language when Jews fled from Germany to the Netherlands in the beginning of the seventeenth century. Since most of these Jews were poor, they came in touch mostly with lower class Dutch people, which caused that their Yiddish language mixed up with the folk language of Dutchmen. Yiddish became more popular over time, but during the nineteenth century Yiddish was banned from the official Dutch language. Nevertheless some words did not disappear, and even appeared in official dictionaries, like for instance the word ‘roddel’, meaning ‘kwaadsprekerij’ or ‘bad talk’ (van der Sijs, 2001: 269-273; de Vries & de Tollenaere, 2002: 308).

 

Of course the act of gossip in Belgium and the Netherlands has a tradition that goes way back much further than the word ‘roddel’. But how did people refer to the act before they called it ‘roddel’? The etymological dictionary of the Dutch language (Het Groot Etymologisch Woordenboek van de Nederlandse Taal, 2003) refers to four main words that can be historically linked to the word ‘roddel’: ‘babbelen’, ‘baker’, ‘anekdote’ and ‘broddelen’. The last word ‘broddelen’ doesn’t explain much, it refers to ‘screw up’ ‘making a mess of something’, and is only related to the word ‘roddelen’ because of structural reasons (b-roddelen) and not because of semantic reasons. The other three words though, all have a semantic connection to ‘roddelen’.

 

The first word ‘babbelen’ has the clearest semantic connection with ‘roddelen’. Current ‘babbelen’ means ‘non-stop talking’, ‘chatting’, a meaning derived from two older connotations of the word. First, ‘babbelen’ used to refer to ‘moving the jaws’, ‘biting’ during the 16th century, and maintained this meaning in some dialects. The movement of the jaws refers to the talking behavior that is related to ‘babbelen’ today. Presently the jaw movement can also be found in the word ‘babbelut’ that has a quite similar structure as ‘babbelen’, and stands for a specific kind of candy that requires a lot of jaw movement. The second ancient meaning of ‘babbelen’ goes back to the Latin word babulus, which means ‘chatting person’. This Latin word was incorporated in many other languages and in Dutch it referred to ‘stamelen’ or ‘stotteren’ which can be translated as ‘to stammer’. ‘Babbelen’ is actually onomatopoeia for unclear speech, like a barbarian. It is also related to the word ‘babbe’ that refers to the proto-language of young children.

 

Now what links the above definitions with the word ‘roddelen’? A variant of the word ‘babbelen’ is ‘blab’ which literally means ‘babbelen, roddelen, zijn mond voorbij praten’, which can be translated as ‘babbling, gossiping’ (Het Groot Etymologisch Woordenboek van de Nederlandse Taal, 2003). In this etymological context I notice no negative connotation of the word ‘roddelen’, but a rather innocent meaning of ‘talking constantly, babbling’.

 

However, a negative connotation is noticed when looking at the etymological connection between the words ‘roddel’ and ‘baker’. This last word's meaning is derived from the 17th century word ‘bakermoe(de)r’, meaning ‘dry-nurse’, which in turn is derived from the 15th century word ‘bakeren’, referring to ‘koesteren, warmhouden’ which can be translated as ‘to coddle, petting’. The second part of the word ‘bakermoeder’, ‘moeder’ simply means ‘mother’, and has dropped out from the word. The connection between the words ‘baker’ and ‘roddel’ can again be found in a derivation form ‘baker’, ‘bakerpraatjes’, meaning in 1898 ‘kletspraat, roddel’, translated as ‘gossip’, but with a negative connotation. It refers to the kind of ‘foolish negative talk’ that was common among dry-nurses (Het Groot Etymologisch Woordenboek van de Nederlandse Taal, 2003). Here we clearly find a negative connotation of the word ‘roddel’, but we have to comment that this etymological record is much more recent (end of 19th century) than the more positive connotation of ‘chatting’, which we found in the word ‘babbelen’. This context of negative talk during childbirth is parallel to the etymological history of the English word ‘gossip’, as I mentioned earlier.

 

The last word that appeared in our etymological search of the word ‘roddel’, ‘anekdote’ first appeared in the 18th century and is derived from the Latin word anecdotum, which means ‘unpublished’. Current the word ‘anecdote’ refers to a ‘short amusing story’. The link with the word ‘roddel’ is an anecdote itself; the Byzantine historicist Prokopius (500-600) wrote seven books that glorified the life of emperor JustinianusI, but the eighth and last book about him was a book full of scandalous stories and gossip about the emperor’s life. Therefore it could not be published before JustinianusI died, and it was called Ane’kdota (Het Groot Etymologisch Woordenboek van de Nederlandse Taal, 2003). The connection between the words ‘roddel’ and ‘anekdote’ lies simply in the fact that the book full of gossip-like stories about JustinianusI was called Anekdota. But looking at the current meanings of both words I see the parallel that both are short amusing stories.

 

Again, to end this historical overview of the Dutch word ‘roddel’, I present the current definition of this word as a noun and as a verb, according to Van Dale’s dictionary (www.vandale.be):

 

rod·del (gossip as a noun)

1 kwaadsprekerij => achterklap, gekonkel, gekonkelfoes, gossip, kletspraat, roddelpraat (evil talk)

2 onwaar bericht, geval van roddel => kletspraatje, roddelpraatje (untrue message)

rod·de·len (gossip as a verb)

1 met genoegen praten over anderen, m.n. in ongunstige zin => iem. over de tong halen, kletsen, konkelen (talking about others with joy, but in negative sense)

 

2.3 From innocent, bonding behavior to negative, scandalous content

 

From this historical overview I conclude that both the words ‘gossip’ and ‘roddel’ have shifted from a focus on innocent social behavior to negative scandalous content. The earlier definitions of gossip stressed a behavioral strategy, the modern definitions focus rather on gossip as a noun than a verb. Still gossip is nowadays used to refer to both an act as well as the content of some of our conversations. In the following section I will outline which current discussions exist on how to define both gossip as a noun and gossip as a verb.

 

 

3 Conceptualizing gossip today

 

3.1 Gossip as a message and an action in current conceptual debates

 

“We all ‘know’ what gossip is, but defining, identifying, and measuring it is a complex enterprise for practical investigation. At the very least, the everyday understanding of the term gossip is included in, but insufficient to encompass the construct as used by researchers. Defining the content, circumstances and functions of gossip will help to put the research methods used to study it into perspective.” (Foster, 2004: 80).

 

“Whether or not experts have been able to concur on a definition of gossip, it is not very difficult to intuitively decide whether something is or isn’t gossip.” (Rosnow & Fine, 1976: 84). Everyone knows what gossip is, until one asks to give a definition of gossip. Thomas (1994) once compared gossip with embroidery; both can be eye-catching and hard to ignore, and both can be covering a large space, but be almost unnoticeable. It is very difficult to define what gossip is and what it is not, conversations are most often a mixture of both.

 

Gossip refers to stories, and gossip means action: “[…] gossip is about something and is something in itself; any study of gossip should consider it as both text and social activity.” (Brenneis, 1989: 226). When defining gossip, it is indeed necessary to differentiate between gossip as an act (‘gossiping’, or ‘to gossip’) and gossip as a noun, ‘a gossip’. Post (1994) also stresses the need to distinguish gossip as a noun and gossip as a verb. Since, as he explains: as an action, gossip unites people and is less threatening than gossip as a noun, which can be malicious and even group-threatening.

 

In what follows I will frame the current aspects of discussion about ‘how to define gossip’ in the discourse of Communication Studies. Before presenting the different aspects of discussion about both gossip as a noun and gossip as a verb, I will indicate how both are related to each other. I frame both aspects of gossip in an information model that links both and highlights which features I should look at.

 

In this chapter I will sometimes briefly touch on Media Gossip as well. However for a more detailed discussion on the definition of media gossip I refer to the last chapter (chapter 7) on Media Gossip.

 

3.2 Framing gossip in communication models

 

“The elements that determine whether information is gossip are the subject, the producer, the recipient, and the relationship between them.” (Smith et al, 1999: 122). Gossip concerns the transmission (gossip as an act) of information (gossip as a noun). Gossip is an act of communication, and as Lasswell (1948: 37, see also figure I.1) said, when studying communication we need to look at 'Who said what to whom, through which channel and with what effect?' I frame my overview of all points of discussion about gossip, in Laswell’s (1948) classical model of information transmission. Although Lasswell focused on mass communication and propaganda, his model is applicable to gossip, both in an interpersonal and mass media context, which both concern the transmit of gossip information.

 

Figure I.1. The Lasswell formula:

 

Who?

Says what?

In what channel?

To whom?

With what effect?

Communicator

Message

Channel

Receiver

Effect

 

Of course criticisms have been given to Lasswell’s model, and other models of information transmission. Relevant to my discussion, are following critiques; first of all the context wherein the transmission takes place is not considered in these models. Secondly, this model looks at the effects of the transmission, but overlooks the intentions of the communicator. Braddock (1958) adjusted Laswell’s formula, to a more extended version where those critics are taken into account (Braddock, 1958, as cited in McQuail & Windahl, 1981). Braddock’s adjustment can be represented as follows:

 

Figure I.2. Braddock’s extension of the Laswell Formula (copied from McQuail & Windahl, 1981: 11)

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Who

 

Says what

 

Through which medium

 

To whom?

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Under what circumstances?

 

 

 

 

 

 

For what purpose?

 

 

 

 

 

 

With what effects?

 

 

 

 

An extra comment, I add, is that even in this extended model of Braddock, the relation between the sender and receiver is not considered. How the sender and receiver are related to each other, will most certainly influence the information transmission between both actors. I therefore opt to add the extra question ‘And how are sender and receiver related to each other?’ to Braddock’s adjusted version of the Lasswell formula.

 

Altogether, I will frame the conceptualisation of gossip according following characteristics; first of all I differentiate for gossip as a noun, which is the message in the transmission model. As I will outline, some of the most severe debates about gossip focus exactly on this content. Next, looking at gossip as an action I will look at disagreements about:

The channel used to dismiss the gossip,

The context wherein this happens,

The actors of gossip (communicator and sender); who gossips?

The relation between those actors,

The motivations of the sender, and,

The effect of the gossip transaction.

 

3.3 Gossip as a message: debates on what gossip content is about

 

Looking at gossip as the message of the information model is looking at gossip as a noun. I do not discuss here the action, but purely the content of what is being transmitted. As much as can be debated on aspects of the act of gossip, the biggest discussions rise when it comes to the content.

 

3.3.1 Gossip: universal themes about human subjects

 

Merry (1984) and Gilmore (1978) say we can gossip about humans or events. But, the first major distinction that differentiates gossip from other forms of communication, such as rumors, is that at least one human subject must be present. Therefore, others (e.g. Foster, 2004; Gelles, 1989; Rosnow & Fine, 1976; Rosnow & Georgoudi, 1985) classify talk about events as ‘rumors’. Gossip concerns personal matters (Nevo & Nevo, 1993) “Have you heard two dogs were fighting in the park yesterday?” is not gossip, whereas “Have you heard John’s dog was fighting with another dog in the park yesterday and he did not interfere?” is gossip. From the moment a human subject is involved in the content, the message is ready to be potentially classified as gossip.

About these human subjects, gossip topics cover a broad range of social matters. Almirol (1981: 295) collected data on gossip among the central Californian Filipinos and concluded that “The most common topics are immorality, love affairs, family quarrels, bankruptcy and other economic matters, inhospitality and rudeness.” Love affairs were also the most common gossip topic in the 18th century French documents that Darnton (1997) analysed. Saunders (1999), concentrating her research on gossip among older women in a support group, concluded that the most discussed topics were (1) fashion, (2) dating, and (3) problems at the Center they were part of. In general we can say that gossip ranges from love issues, (Gelles, 1989; Levin & Kimmel, 1977; Spacks, 1985), to health (Percival, 2000; Smith et al, 1999) and many other person-related aspects.

 

McGill (1968) says that universal themes, that appeal to a broad audience score best in information transmission. Divale and Seda (1999) did a cross-cultural analysis of gossip topics, among 136 societies, that are listed in both the Standard Cross-Cultural Sample and the Human Relations Area Files. They came up with a list of 24 gossip topics that occur cross-culturally. Using a factor analysis they could cluster these topics to three primary factors, and five secondary factors. An overview of their 24 topics and how these can be clustered can be found in table I.1.

 

Their three primary factors, which are ‘general gossip’, ‘political gossip’, and ‘machismo gossip’, make sense concerning classification of specific topics. The five secondary ones might look a little confusing, such as gossip about ‘cattle’ in combination with ‘marriage’. The authors explain that cattle are often used as a bride price and this explains the combination. Also combining ‘religion’ with ‘farming’ seems to make little sense, but Divale and Seda (1999) argue that a lot of farming involves religious rituals.

 

Their research is a nice overview of what can be considered as cross-cultural occurring gossip topics. However, the presentation of their analysis misses more detailed descriptions of the 24 categories. For instance, gossip about ‘cattle’, can only be called gossip if it is talk about a certain person’s property of cattle. As I just explained, gossip requires human subjects, we do not gossip about non-human things, such as animals. Therefore the study of Divale and Seda (1999) should be looked at with a certain scepticism. Their relevance for the discussion here is that their analysis confirms the existence of a cross-cultural broad range of topics that are present in gossip conversations.

 

Since gossip is about social matters it is often denigrated as being ‘small talk’, not delving into deep issues. (Ayim, 1994; Morreall, 1994). In later chapters, I will contradict this claim and argue that gossip even plays a crucial part in everyone’s life. To finish here, I suggest that, when defining gossip, a clear restriction about the presence of at least one human subject (or gossipee) should be made, but no restriction should be made about what is being said about this gossipee. Gossip is about all traits and behaviors of a certain person, or multiple persons.

 

Table I.1. Divale and Seda’s 24 topics of gossip across 136 societies classified into 8 factors

 

Factor name (if

Topic of gossip given)

General gossip

On men

 

Neighbors

 

Socializing and news

 

Women

Political Gossip

Topics of family

 

Government and colonial affairs

 

Politics

Machismo gossip

Boasting

 

Hunting

 

Laziness

 

Wife beating

Factor 4

Adultery

 

Scandal

Factor 5

Drinking

 

Murder and assault

Factor 6

Bride price

 

Dowry

Factor 7

Farming

 

Religion

Factor 8

Cattle

 

Marriage

 

3.3.2 The subject of gossip: who do we gossip about

 

Looking in more detail to the gossiped subjects, or gossipees, I noticed some critical points of discussions between researchers that can be relevant to take notice of in my conceptualisation process. First of all, most gossip is about living human beings, but we cannot exclude the dead from gossip conversations. People talk, and gossip about dead people as well (Gilmore, 1978). We do not gossip if we talk about Little Red Riding Hood, therefore fictional characters can be excluded. However, people who once existed can be subject of gossip.

 

Next, a more elaborated discussion focuses on how known the gossipees should be to the gossipers. Noon & Delbridge (1993) think gossip is restricted to talk about members of one’s social setting “… thus speculation about the private lives of royalty, for example, would fall outside of our definition and could be considered ‘idle chatter’.” (Noon & Delbridge, 1993: 25). Hannerz (1967) is a little less strict, leaving open some option to gossip about celebrities as well. He says that gossipers need some minimal awareness about the gossiped subject. This is, the gossipee should be identifiable to the gossipers. And:

 

“Thus it is possible to gossip about movie stars and royalty, although one does not interact with them in face-to-face relationships. On the other hand, talking about an unknown man whom one passed in the street once is not gossip according to this view.” (Hannerz, 1967: 39)

 

So, according to Hannerz we need not to restrict gossip as strictly, as Noon and Delbridge suggest, to only gossipees that are part of the social network of the gossipers, but a little restriction has to be made. Gossip about non-celebrity people who are not part of the gossipers’ social network is excluded from Hannerz’ definition, since these people are in no sense identifiable to the gossipers.

 

Still, looking at Ben-Ze’ev’s (1994) classification of gossipees: “The objects of gossip fall into three major groups: (a) people in our immediate surroundings, (b) famous people, and (c) people whose intimate and personal lives are unique.” (Ben-Ze’ev, 1994: 17). In this statement I find an argument to incorporate non-celebrity and non identifiable gossipees in the general definition of gossip. Subjects can become gossipees if they have a unique feature about them. I agree with Ben-Ze’ev and also say that we can gossip about people we do not know. To clarify my statement, consider the following conversation:

 

Anne: “Have you heard the story about that Kung Fu chick?!”

Maggie: “No, tell me!”

Anne: “Well, she was walking her dog in a park, in the afternoon, when a guy jumped on her back, trying to cut her throat! Luckily she was able to react very fast; it seems that she was a skilled Kung Fu fighter or something like that! Anyway, she seriously attacked the guy, even managed to tie him up with her dog’s leach, and brought him to the police station.”

Maggie: “Oh, what serendipity!”

Anne: “Yes, sure, since that guy seemed to be the one who killed another girl on campus last month!”

 

Two girls discussing what happened to another girl and a guy they both don’t know. If we restrict gossip to information about known gossipees, than this conversation is not gossip. Still, what we call ‘gossip magazines’ are covered with such stories. I think these conversations are very much the same as any other gossip conversation about known gossipees. Overall I therefore propose not to make any restrictions concerning the gossipees in my general conceptual definition. We gossip about everyone, known people and unknowns. As Almirol (1981) says: “Gossip is viewed as a social equalizer; everybody gossips and everybody can be subjected to gossip.” (298). There is a ‘but’ to this, as he argues, though: “But there are persons who are more likely to be gossiped about than not. Persons who are regarded as constant violators of social values are dealt with promptly and vigorously through gossip.” (Almirol, 1981: 298).

 

As I will argue later in this and other chapters, I think a classification of gossip is necessary to resolve all discussions and make future research on gossip more clear and comparable. Almirol (1981) mentions that violators of social norms will be more likely to become gossipees. My chapters on the social uses and evolutionary explanations for gossip (chapters 3 and 4) will delve deeper into this matter. Here I want to outline a general definition which I will use for my contribution to a better understanding of gossip.

 

3.3.3 Can a gossiper be a gossipee as well

 

Rosnow & Fine (1976) define gossip as: “news about the affairs of another, one’s own memoirs or confessions, or any hearsay of a personal nature, be it positive or negative, spoken or in print.” (Rosnow & Fine, 1976: 87). And Almirol says that: “[…] gossip is always done behind the subject’s back. An important rule in gossip is never to confront the person face-to-face.” (Almirol, 1981: 297). I use these citations to open a next point of discussion; do we restrict gossip to talk about absent others, or do we also include talk about the behavior of present persons?

 

Most researchers (e.g. Arno, 1980; Ayim, 1994; Bergmann, 1993; de Vries, 1990; Eder & Enke, 1991; Foster, 2004; Gelles, 1989; Hannerz, 1967; Kuttler, et al, 2002; Merry, 1984; Morreall, 1994; Nevo & Nevo, 1993; Spacks, 1982, 1985; Wert & Salovey, 2004b; Young, 2001) claim that gossip is the telling of tales about absent others. Foster (2004) even argues this to be the only restriction necessary to classify a conversational message as gossip. In his recent overview of the most important studies of gossip, he says: “So the absence of the third party seems to be a minimal and, for many, sufficient requirement.” (Foster, 2004: 81).

 

Other researchers (Rosnow and Fine 1976, 1978; Dunbar, 1998a; Fox, 2001; Gilmore, 1978; Medini & Rosenberg, 1976) clearly disagree with Foster and others, and even take the totally opposite positions in this discussion, by saying that people can even gossip about themselves.

 

I opt for a middle-road position. I agree with the comments of Foster (2004) and Kuttler et al (2002) who argue to call gossip about yourself self-disclosure. Gossiping about yourself is a contradiction in terms, I think. Gossip is talk about other persons. Talking about yourself might be very similar to gossip and can even be used to reach similar goals, but I do agree with most researchers to restrict the definition of gossip to talk about others, and not the self. However, I am not as strict as most researchers, who declare that gossipees can never be present in conversations. It happens that, when talking in a group, someone suddenly starts talking about one of the participants to all others. “Hey pardon me, in case you might not have noticed, I am standing next to you!” Have you never uttered this expression, when you where made fun of in front of a whole group?

 

Foster (2004) and Kuttler et al (2002) suggest to call information about present others ‘disclosure’, but I do not see why this kind of talk about the traits and behavior of a third person cannot be labelled as gossip. The only further restriction I make is that the gossip cannot be addressed directly and solely to the recipient if this person is the gossipee as well. This is, we can gossip about present others, but those others should be third persons. “Did you know you are such a clumsy person?!” uttered in a dyadic interaction is not gossip. It is directly transmitted to the receiver, who here is a gossipee as well. I agree to call this disclosure. However, if Ann tells Suzy ‘Did you know Margareth is such a clumsy person!?” while Margaret is present at the moment of transmission, I do consider this to be gossip.

 

I therefore restrict the gossipee(s) to ‘third’ persons, with no restriction of absence; the gossipee as third person can either be absent or present at the time of the information transmission. But with a restriction of being an active member of the conversation: gossipees cannot gossip about themselves, they cannot be senders of gossip. Nor can they be receivers of gossip; the gossip message cannot be addressed to them personally. They can be physically present when two or more gossipers gossip about him or her, but cannot be an active participant of the conversation.

 

3.3.4 Is gossip good, bad or both

 

“My favorite letter of those I received when newspapers proclaimed my belief that “gossip is good for you” came from a woman who assured me I would sell more books if I alleged instead that gossip is bad for you.” (Spacks, 1985: 258)

 

In her article ‘In praise of gossip’, Patricia Meyer Spacks (1982) has mixed feelings concerning the goodness or badness of gossip. Gossip can be healing for the teller, but can seriously damage the reputation of those gossiped about, and: “[t]he trouble is that no clear line divides what I’ve called “good” gossip from what I’ve called “bad”: they inhabit a continuum. One can slide from one to the other, and then slide back again.” (Spacks, 1982: 36).

 

The debate about whether gossip is ‘good’, ‘bad’, or both is maybe the biggest issue researchers and laypeople argue about. de Vries (1990) defines gossip clearly as talk with a negative connotation. Baumeister, Zhang and Vohs (2004) say that psychologists in general show little respect for gossip, by attaching a negative connotation to it: “Psychology has not generally had much respect for gossip. The traditional and prevailing view has regarded it as an indirect form of aggression, akin to teasing.” (Baumeister, Zhang and Vohs, 2004: 112).

 

When asking the elderly people he observed to describe ‘gossip’, Percival (2000) noted that most of his respondents would say it is ‘bad talk’, even though his analysis showed that among these elderly both negative and positive gossip flourished. The everyday meaning of gossip has a pejorative sense of an undesirable action, engaged by those who don’t have better things to do, as I explained in the etymological overview. Still, as Arno (1980) comments, the anthropological definition of gossip is broader than this, defining gossip as “the informal circulation of information about and evaluation of people’s behavior” (Arno, 1980: 344), both positive and negative talk are included.

 

And indeed, in spite of its negative reputation in the common sense use, researchers of gossip (e.g. Ben-Ze’ev, 1994; Fine & Rosnow, 1978; Goodman & Ben-Ze’ev, 1994; Rosnow & Fine, 1976; Spacks, 1985) agree that gossip cannot always be described as malicious. Gossip is not necessarily negative talk. It is the exchange of social information about who is doing what to whom (Dunbar, 1998a; Fox, 2001; Rosnow & Fine, 1976). Studies, such as the above mentioned study of Percival (2000) among elderly people, or studies among children (Kuttler et al, 2002) all conclude that both admiring and pejorative statements are made in gossip. The study that came up with the most convincing evidence to argue this debate so far, is the study of Levin and Arluke (1985), who eavesdropped on the conversations of male and female college students. These researchers concluded that gossip could both have clearly positive (27%) and negative (25%) references towards other people, but that most gossip did not even have a clear connotation.

 

To rule out misunderstandings, should we use different words to refer to ‘good’ and ‘bad’ gossip? Some have suggested this and do so. For instance Gelles (1989) who talks about ‘scandal’, when referring to bad gossip. Or Guendouzi (2001), who differentiates for ‘harmless’ and ‘malicious’ gossip. The first she calls ‘peer group news-giving’ and the latter ‘bitching’. Collins (1994) keeps the word ‘gossip’ for bad talk and invents the new word ‘quossip’ to refer to the discourse that is similar to gossip, but lacks the malicious aspects. Also Spacks (1985) labels them differently: naming them ‘serious gossip’, and ‘malicious gossip’. The trouble with redefining for two different kinds of gossip is that this puts gossip in a clear black-and-white frame, while in reality different shades of grey lie in-between both extremes (Spacks, 1985).

 

Researchers have tried to explain why gossip has such a negative connotation. All of the arguments used are related to other points of discussion, as I will discuss later, such as Ben-Ze’ev’s (1994) claim that the ‘bad’ attached to gossip is due to the consequences, or effects gossip can have. de Sousa (1994) suggests that the bad connotation of gossip comes from the power relation between the actors. Gossip is a very powerful tool, and just like other kinds of power, it is feared and condemned. According to Sulls (1977) the recent negative association with gossip is because of the inherent unreliability of gossip. And last, Almirol (1981) states that gossip is bad talk; with bad intentions of the gossiper. This shows that all points of discussion I outline here are interrelated. In chapter 5 I will further argue that negative loaded gossip might be recalled more often, because of the so-called negativity bias (see chapter 5, section 4.1.5).

 

To end the good/bad discussion I conclude that gossip can both be good or bad, dependent on how you define ‘gossip’. The good sense of gossip is incorporated in the broader definition of gossip, the bad connotation characterizes the narrower, more common definition (Taylor, 1994), and for a scientific approach to study gossip it is best to take a neutral position, letting both options remain open (Kurland & Pelled, 2000). Therefore I make no restrictions on the connotation of gossip in my general conceptual definition.

 

Yet, ending this part of discussion, I also want to mention a practical solution to decide whether gossip is good, bad or both. In order to gossip ‘good’, or as Westacott (2000) calls it ‘ethical’, he outlines us some easy guidelines. He summed up a few questions one has to answer for him- or herself, that indicate whether a gossip story is ethical to spread around or not. A schematic overview of these decisions can be found in figure I.3.

 

Figure I.3. A guide to ethical gossip (copied from Kreiter, 2003: 56)

 

 

 

Is it a lie?

YES

Unethical

 

 

NO

 

 

 

 

Does it violate someone’s rights?

YES

Unethical

 

 

NO

 

 

 

 

Does it disregard someone’s claims?

YES

Unethical

 

 

NO

 

 

 

 

Does it directly promote more harm

than good?

YES

Unethical

 

 

NO

 

 

Ethical

YES

Does it directly promote more good than harm?

 

 

 

 

NO

 

 

Ethical

NO

Is it contrary to the wishes of the subject?

 

 

 

 

YES

 

 

Ethical

YES

Is it merely contrary to the subject’s hopes?

 

 

 

3.3.5 How much can we believe from the gossip we hear

 

Sulls (1977) once said that the negative connotation of gossip is caused by the unreliable character of gossip. “Have you heard Prof. Cramer is cheating on his wife with one of his students?!” How do we know this information is true? Is all gossip true, is it all lies, or also somewhere in between? Or, more precisely, can we classify unreliable information as ‘gossip’?

 

Some researchers assert that most gossip is untrue, and even when it is true, it has been manipulated in one way or another (e.g. Klinghoffer, 1994). That gossip occurs among trusted individuals, however, has prompted other researchers to state that gossip can be regarded as reliable information (Andersen, 1995; Bergmann, 1993; Gelles, 1989; Smith, et al, 1999). Gossip conversations take place between people who know each other, and trust each other. I trust you, therefore I can convey to you this information that other people don’t know yet.

 

Dissemination of gossip among trusted individuals differentiates gossip from rumors, which are often spread freely among interested parties without fear of punishment from possible offended parties. Rumors lack reliability compared to gossip because the latter occurs in trust relationships (Bergmann, 1993; Foster, 2004; Orr, 1999; Smith et al, 1999). In their analysis of the spread of the (false) rumor of the death of Paul McCartney in the media, Rosnow and Fine (1974) also comment that gossip and rumor are very closely related to each other, but differ significantly, because of the fact that rumors are always unsubstantiated and gossip might or might not be a known fact. I go along with their idea to restrict my gossip definition.

 

In my opinion gossip can both be true or false, since language in general can be truthful or false (Barkow, 1989). To identify gossip from rumors, I suggest calling ‘gossip’ information of which the sender has a substantiated true/false knowledge. This is to say that the sender should not doubt the true/falseness of gossip. “Have you heard, …” is an introduction to gossip. The sender knows (sure or almost sure) that the content of the message is true or false (a lie). Whereas “I have heard, but am not sure if it is true…” introduces rumors. When the sender cannot take a position whether the information is true or not, I do not label it as gossip, but refer to this as rumors.

 

Remark that even when the sender knows for himself or herself that the information is true or not, this does not imply that the receiver has the same true/false knowledge. The receiver of gossip can distrust the sender, and since gossip covers true information and lies, he or she must be careful in believing the sender. Because the receiver lacks the true/false knowledge and seeks reliability, repeatedly hearing the same information can be valuable.

 

3.3.6 What did you say? How new does gossip have to be

 

Of course we are all curious to hear the latest gossip. Information already heard is less likely to surprise its receiver. Gossip preferably is new information. ‘New’ does not mean that the gossiped-about event happened recently, but that the information had been unknown by the receiver prior to hearing it. For instance, the headline “Prince Charles killed Lady Di!” appeared in the media in 2003, six years after Lady Diana past away in a car accident in August 1997. It happened a long time ago, but the information (true or not) was new to everyone. Who could have imagined this to be the case? Therefore the ‘news’ or gossip hit the front pages of many tabloids. So gossip does not necessarily need to be ‘new’ in the sense that what is being told occurred recently. Still, there is a second aspect about the news value of gossip I need to clarify.

 

Hearing the same piece of gossip more than once can have benefits for the receiver. Since, hearing this same story again from additional, independent sources adds credibility to the story. Hess and Hagen (2002, 2004b) found that reiteration of a gossip statement about a young, female celebrity increased the believability of the gossip, but only for research subjects who were relatively uninterested in the gossip. They also found that adding information to a gossip-worthy event that suggested benign alternative interpretations of the event made the gossip less believable, but that increasing the number of sources of the gossip (and still including the information that suggested a benign interpretation of the gossip) increased the believability of the gossip.

 

In summary, the first time a receiver hears a piece of gossip, this gossip is high in news value and low in credibility value. As exposure to the same gossip story increases, the credibility will increase, but the effect of added credibility decreases. In other words, the jump in credibility between hearing a story twice and three times is larger than the jump in credibility between hearing a story ten times and eleven times. The relationship between credibility and exposure can be represented with a diminishing curved regression line. Gossip has high news value the first time it is heard; news value drops quickly with exposure to the same story, but credibility value increases slowly with exposure to the same story. I present a model of how this could be presented in a graph in figure I.4. Note that this is a suggestive model, and not based on actual data.

 

Figure I.4. News- and credibility value for the receiver who is exposed multiple times to the same piece of gossip (model, no real data)

 

3.4 Gossip as an action: the transmission model of gossip

 

Now that I have more or less explained what gossip is about as a message, I will overview which characteristics of the transmission of such information raise discussions among laypeople and researchers.

 

3.4.1 From mouth to media: gossip channels

 

The most common and oldest form of gossip is of course interpersonal, face-to-face gossip, communicated through oral channels. It always was, and still is a fact that the majority of our conversations occur between and about people who know each other. We talk most to and about our relatives, friends and acquaintances (Emler, 1994). Already referring to the context, which I discuss next, interpersonal gossip occurs in very small groups of participants who know each other fairly well (Ayim, 1994).

 

But we can’t deny the fact that in our modern societies, gossip also comes via a new, and very public channel: mass media. Other researchers (e.g. Levin & Kimmel, 1977; Nevo & Nevo, 1993; Riegel, 1996; Rosnow & Fine, 1976) have already paid attention to this media gossip, which is today omnipresent: tabloids, gossip columns in newspapers, gossip in soaps, real life television, gossip television programs, the latest and hottest facts spread in radio programs, etc. If you have a television, a radio, if you read any kind of written media product, or if you walk around in our Western cities crowed with billboards you are confronted with gossip, whether you like this or not.

 

But is media gossip really gossip? This question is examined in the debate about the channels used to transfer gossip. “Madonna is constantly on a diet”, “Jude Law is the sexiest man on earth”, is this gossip? Morreall (1994) claims that gossip is always private and always occurs behind-the scenes, certainly in the eyes of those who gossip. That is why “gossip-columns” are misnamed, he says; they are not about gossip. Though others, like Rosnow and Fine (1976) do define celebrity stories as gossip.

 

The central issue of this discussion about whether we can call information exchange ‘gossip’ depending on which channel is used to transmit the content, does not focus on the fact that the gossip is printed, instead of orally transmitted, but has to do with the scale of the audience. Gossip spread by mass media reaches far more individuals than interpersonal gossip. The typical, small scale trust-based relation between sender and receiver is replaced by an anonymous transaction between a journalist, who is unknown to most of his audience, and a reader. The discussion slides here to the actors of gossip; who can take part?

 

3.4.2 Actors of gossip: who can take part

 

The participants of a gossip transaction are a characteristic of the act of gossip, which researchers have defined differently. The first points of discussion are; is every one of us a gossiper, or are gossipers different from non-gossipers? Next, there is an argument about how many people can take part in a gossip conversation, and lastly it has been questioned whether gossipers are all women or if men gossip as well.

 

Let me start with the first issue: does everyone gossip? Yerkovich (1977) sets out a spectrum to define different kinds of gossipers. On the one extreme she lists the ‘benign’ gossipers, who will occasionally pass on information. Benign gossipers create a congenial situation to gossip. The other side of the spectrum is occupied by the ‘gossips’, who love gossip so much that everyone thinks these people will talk to anyone about anything. In between you have the troublemakers, who either unconsciously (“Unwitting Troublemaker”) repeat what has been said in a conversation, or those who deliberately (“Knowing Troublemaker”) repeat information to stir things up. These troublemaking gossipers create uncongenial situations to gossip. Yerkovich (1977) does not, however, say whether some people are totally restricted from gossip. She outlines a nice spectrum of different kinds of gossipers, but this does not answer the question if all of us gossip, or if I need to restrict my definition of gossip in terms of specific personality traits.

 

Ben-Ze’ev (1994) does mention people who never gossip, he says those are the people with little or no interest in other people in general. While, those who do gossip are:

 

“The typical gossipmonger is intelligent, with a good memory and an ability to discern connections between events. Gossips are quite realistic people; their extensive knowledge of embarrassing events prevents them from being naïve. Gossips are often quite sensitive, curious, social-minded, and involved.” (Ben-Ze’ev, 1994: 19)

 

In line with his statement, Nevo and Nevo (1993) found that people with vocational interests scored higher than people with no vocational interest on their scale that measured a general tendency to gossip. Still, Ben-Ze’ev’s description of gossipers is so very general, and applicable to anyone, that it cannot be used to restrict gossipers from non-gossipers. I think a better description of non-gossipers comes from Merry (1984). She says that:

 

“In general, people who ignore gossip are those who have significantly greater or lesser power and resources: those who are not subject to the economic and political control of those gossiping about them, those who are not entirely dependent on their local community for political support, economic assistance, or irreplaceable social relationships, and those who can leave the community easily.” (Merry, 1984: 286)

 

So people who never engage in gossip are almost socially isolated people, who do not need, or want to depend on others. True, I agree that hermits will not engage in gossip as they do not even have someone to gossip to, or about. But to a certain degree, all of us depend on others, and everyone is socially engaged. Humans are social creatures, so Merry’s (1984) description of non-gossipers might be true, but hard to find in reality. I agree with her opinion, in the sense that for instance, a boss of a firm, who has significant greater power and resources and can easily replace those who work for him, might not engage in gossip at his work. But this does not mean that, when he comes home to his family, where he is socially engaged, he will not refrain from gossiping about his children to his wife, to keep up with what is going on when he leaves the house.

 

Brown (1991) listed gossip as a ‘Human Universal’. Indeed, the anthropological records on gossip indicate that gossip occurs in any society, not depending on cultural restraints, flourishing among youths, adults and elderly. This suggests gossip is inherent to any human individual. I will discuss this more in detail when I come to the evolutionary approach to gossip. But so far, for this discussion on the definition of gossip, I think that people who never engage in gossip are hard to find. Anyone who grows up in a social environment will become a gossiper. Here, where I focus on restrictions to define gossip, it is sufficient to say that I do not need to set out restrictions about the actors of a gossip transmission.

 

Next, how big can a group of gossipers be? Some (Merry, 1984; Spacks, 1985) claim that we can only talk about gossip when the conversation occurs in small groups of gossipers, since gossip is such a private form of communication. But exactly how small is small? Do we talk about five people, fifteen, or even thirty when talking about small groups? Spacks (1982) numbered ‘small’ to three people. She says that within these small groups of three people good gossip occurs, whereas in bigger groups more bad gossip is going on. I think this is a little exaggerated. If we think about lunch time with colleagues, or reunions with old school members, or dinner parties with friends, and recently, gossip via e-mail, where gossip occurs among a bunch of people, it is not all bad talk that flourishes. “Hey do you know what became of Mary?”, “Have you heard what happened to Cathy yesterday, when she was interrogated by our boss?”, these are typical start-offs of gossip conversations, which do not have bad intentions, and most often occur in larger social settings than three gossipers.

 

I do not think I need to restrict the definition of gossip with a numerical count of maximum number of participants. Physical constraints, such as our vocal and hearing capacity might restrict our conversational group size (Dunbar, Duncan & Nettle, 1995) in a face-to-face setting, obliging us to use other channels if we want to reach a greater audience. I therefore think that restrictions of group size depend on which channels are used to transmit the gossip information. This leads us again to the discussion about interpersonal- and media gossip. I already argued that both can be considered as classifiable as ‘gossip’, and suggest that it might be useful to differentiate both by using different labels (Interpersonal- vs. Media Gossip), but no further restrictions are required.

Third, and lastly, concerning the actors of gossip:

 

“If two people engage in the same behavior, talking too much, the woman is likely to be called a gossip, while the man will not. Ironically, a man who talks too much is often called “an old woman”, a phrase that manages to blame womankind for man’s verbosity.” (Rysman, 1977: 179)

 

In the common sense, gossip is often linked to female talk. I already pointed out in the etymological overview, that this is quite a recent phenomenon. Gossip used to refer to both male and female activities, but today not only the common sense, but also studies tend to claim that gossip is typical feminine. Percival (2000) noticed that gossip occurred more frequent among female than male elderly people, but must admit that most of the elderly living in the sheltered housing he observed were female, which might have biased his results. Still, among the Californian Filipinos Almirol (1981) observed, both gossipers and gossipees were mostly women. But others disagree, for instance Gelles (1989), who describes the case study of an 18th century courtship affair wherein a man is not only the main gossiped subject, but also an active participant.

 

The whole discussion about sex differences in gossip is too large of a subject to fully outline here. I will discuss sex differences in gossip more profoundly in chapter 4 and chapter 6, where I outline the functions of gossip, and how gossip develops over a lifespan. The whole debate about sex differences is irrelevant to be able to define gossip. Even if women would gossip more than men, this does not mean that men do not engage in it at all. To define gossip as ‘women talk’ is therefore wrong in my opinion. It is not merely women’s talk, as both men and women are gossipers. A general definition of gossip must embody both sexes, and have no restrictions based on the sex of gossipers.

 

From all discussable characteristics about the actors of gossip, I conclude that no restrictions should be made on the definition of gossip as an act when it comes to the characteristics of the gossipers. Everyone engages in gossip sometimes, both men and women, of all cultures and ages. Concerning the group size of gossipers, I suggest differentiating for Interpersonal Gossip (IG), where group size is limited, and Media Gossip (MG), which is spread to a very broad public.

 

3.4.3 The context wherein gossip is transmitted

 

The same story transmitted in different contexts can either be gossip or some other form of communication (Fine & Rosnow, 1978; Hannerz 1967; Rosnow & Georgoudi, 1985):

 

“One intriguing characteristic of gossip on which most researchers would probably agree is its ‘contextualist’ nature; that is, the meaning of gossip is to a high degree a property of the context in which it is situated.” (Rosnow & Georgoudi, 1985: 59)

 

Indeed, little discussion is going on about whether the context wherein the information is spread determines if we can talk about gossip or not. The context is extremely important and will define if information is gossip or not. Using the general, anthropological definition of gossip, that defines gossip as any exchange of information about personal features or behaviors of a third person (Arno, 1980) I will show how this definition lacks a contextual restriction. Since, if I tell you “My sister brushed her teeth this morning”, and “My dad took off in his car”, would you consider this to be gossip? Probably not, and chances that you will further spread this around are low. Still, these lines report about the traits and behaviors of third persons, which according to Arno (1980) should be gossip. Now imagine you live in a society where no one ever brushes his or her teeth, and not a single person has a car. Imagine, living in this society, someone tells you “My sister brushed her teeth this morning”, and “My dad took off in his car”. In this totally different context, the same information suddenly gets a completely different value, and it will be much more likely that the receiver will spread this news around further, and people won’t deny this to be gossip. This is because the same information is more likely to elicit feelings of surprise in the second context. I will discuss in section 3.4.5 of this chapter (see below) that ‘surprise’ is an important criterion to restrict some talk from gossip.

 

Note that, as Foster (2004) comments, the context cannot be separated from the content of what is gossiped about. “The situational aspect of gossip cannot be entirely separated from the content of the gossip, any more than the functions of gossip can be separated from the form; the inherent meaning of the content depends on these other factors.” (Foster, 2004: 83). I quote Foster to stress again that although I overview all critical points of discussion separately they are all very related to each other. From this specific debate about the context, I conclude that in the definition of gossip, something should be mentioned about the effect of the context wherein the transaction takes place.

 

3.4.4 Relations between gossipers: are doctors gossiping about their patients

 

The next discussable aspect of gossip transmission concerns the relationship between the gossipers. The question here is if I should exclude the transmission of information about the behavior of others, because of relational aspects between the actors. Some (Handelman, 1973; Hannerz, 1967) say answer to this question is: yes, restrictions are needed. Since, very similar to context factors:

 

“The same information may be gossip or non-gossip depending on who gives it to whom; the communication that Mrs. A’s child is illegitimate is not gossip if it is occurring between two social workers acting in that capacity, while it is gossip if Mrs. A’s neighbors talk about it.” (Hannerz, 1967: 36)

 

Who transmits the information very much defines if we can classify it as gossip or not (Handelman, 1973: 224): “[t]his states simply that the form of how an encounter develops tends to define the social meaning of information introduced within.” According to this opinion for example, doctors discussing the health condition of a patient are not gossiping. Two managers discussing the capability of candidates for a job application are not gossiping. Nor are two teachers discussing the problematic behavior of one of their pupils. But as soon they start talking about the candidates or pupils to their wives or even other colleagues later that day, they are gossiping. The relation between the gossipers is restricted to the private sphere according to this view on gossip.

 

I, however, do not think this restriction is necessary. Two doctors talking about their patients are gossiping, as well as teachers and managers are gossiping about their pupils and job applicants. The functions I will attribute to gossip in chapter 4 are applicable to these specific situations. I see no reason to exclude these conversations from the discourse of gossip. As I will also outline in chapter 7, where I focus on Media Gossip, this might have some repercussions to gossip present in Media Gossip.

 

A second restriction to the relationship between gossipers, that has been suggested, is to exclude conversations with people we don’t know. Smith et al (1999) call the gossip-like conversations with strangers ‘rumors’: “The most significant distinction between the concepts of rumor and gossip is not the information that is shared but the relationship of the people who are communicating the information.” (Smith et al, 1999: 121). In line with Smith et al’s comment, Almirol (1981) says: “[o]ne gossips only with someone whom one knows well. One never gossips with a stranger.” (Almirol, 1981: 294). I disagree with both Smith et al and Almirol. All of us can think about situations, where you find yourself gossiping to a person you don’t know. Receptions, dinner parties, new colleagues, and so on, are situations where you easily end up talking, and eventually gossiping to a stranger. Most of these times people (automatically) seek mutual acquaintances to gossip about “So, you are a friend of Rob, where do you know him from?", “So, you also went to College in Bristol, then you might know Sharon Hearst?”, and soon your conversation will shift to ‘exchanging information about a third person’. People seek mutual acquaintances to talk about, to gossip about. As Yerkovich (1977) says, gossipers do not necessarily need to be friends, but must have mutual interests or subjects to talk about.

 

As I will argue in my seventh and last chapter of this theoretical part of my dissertation, celebrities play an important part in this. Nowadays we often talk about celebrities as mutual acquaintances. This celebrity gossip is actually a combination of both Interpersonal Gossip (IG) and Media Gossip (MG). It is interpersonal, occurring between two or more people face-to-face, and it is most often based on information than comes from the mass media.

 

So, a restriction that says the gossipers should know each other would be wrong, in my opinion. Therefore, I conclude that concerning the relation between gossipers, I should not restrict the definition of gossip with criteria concerning the relationship between the gossipers.

 

3.4.5 When gossip hits you: motivations of the sender and effect on the receiver of gossip

 

“Gossip is not merely ‘idle chatter’ (the common definition), but small talk with social purpose.” (Rosnow, 1977: 158). What Rosnow claims, when saying this, is that the sender of gossip has intentions and is motivated to reach a certain goal by spreading the gossip. Spacks (1982) and Klinghoffer (1994) as well thinks that gossip senders should have a purpose to gossip. More specifically for this debate on the definition of gossip, Thomas (1994) claims that the motives of the gossipers define whether something can be considered gossip or not. He lists three important motives: (1) when people comment on the behavior of others, (2) when people want to vent negative feelings, and (3) when information about the violation of norms and social protocols is transmitted. The last two motives to gossip will be discussed, along with others, in my next chapters, wherein I will discuss the use of gossip in our daily lives.

 

The question I have to ask here is whether Thomas’ (1994) claim is correct or not. Do gossipers need to have specific motives to gossip, or can gossip also occur without any intentions? His first motive that people want to make comments on the behavior of others seems reasonable, but doesn’t add much to the whole discussion about how to define gossip. All researchers agree that gossip is information about the behavior (or characteristics) of a third person, so his argument that people want to comment on this is quite obvious. What is relevant to question is whether these comments need to be consciously motivated or not. That is to say, do we need to restrict gossip to conscious comments on the traits and behaviors of others?

 

Nevo and Nevo (1993) say that gossip does not always involve a conscious purpose. I agree with this. Many gossip conversations occur unconsciously to the gossipers, especially if no negative comments are transmitted. Limiting gossip to consciously motivated talk, would leave out most of the innocent and good-natured chitchat. I even think that the negative connotation of gossip comes from the fact that negative gossip happens more consciously and therefore is more noticeable and remembered (see also chapter 5, section 4.1.5).

 

Conscious or unconscious, what the gossiper transmits to the receiver will have some effect. The question here is whether we can restrict gossip from other forms of conversations in terms of the effect it has on the receiver. The most common effect gossip has on a receiver is eliciting feelings of ‘surprise’. “Really?”, “What?!”, “Can’t be true?!”, “You must be kidding me!”, are typical responses people give when hearing gossip. Most often gossip senders start their message with “You will never believe this, but…”, “You must hear this…”. Gossip feeds our curiosity: “Curiosity is a feature shared by all gossipers. […] Maybe curiosity so directed is in itself a virtue lacking in those who do not engage in gossip.” (Taylor, 1994: 42). A reason for this might be that:

 

“[…] gossip about the characteristics of a person as inferred from observed actions [also] seems more valuable when it is felt that these actions are either not frequently experienced in everyday interaction with him or not the characteristics which he attempts to show in such interaction. Thus gossip is often information which deals with the discrepancies between ‘impression’ and ‘reality’ concerning a person. The less such a discrepancy exists, the less likely is it that the person involved is a favored object of gossip.” (Hannerz, 1967: 38)

 

True, we do not often gossip about the traits and behaviors that do not surprise us. As I mentioned with the example of “My sister brushes her teeth”, this can only be classified as gossip in a context where no one else brushes his teeth, and where this kind of behavior surprises recipients. I therefore suggest incorporating the surprise effect in the definition of gossip, since it restricts gossip from other conversations both on contextual and effect aspects.

 

However: “Did you know John started a fight last weekend because he was drunk again?!” If John is a regular drinker, who often starts fights, this information might not surprise his friends and acquaintances. Still, it will be very likely that they will talk, or gossip about it. It is talk about the behavior of a third person, and it is behavior that differs from what an average person does. Again, if John would live among all people who drink and fight, it is less likely they will discuss what happened last week.

 

Surprise alone is therefore not a sufficient restriction to differentiate gossip from other conversational forms. I therefore add deviance to the restrictions of my general definition. Either the information transmitted through gossip elicits feelings of surprise in the recipient or, if this is not the case, the gossiped about trait or behavior should be different from what any other average person does.

 

 

4 Classifying gossip

 

It seems to me that most of the scientific debate about gossip does not rest on fundamental disagreements between researchers, but is rather due to poor definitions of gossip. A very beautiful illustration of how redefining gossip can lead to better understanding of it, follows from the study of Gilmore (1978). He identified eleven different kinds of gossip, that each are given a different meaning in Fuenmajor, a small city in Andalusia, Spain. The Fuenmayoreños even have a different name for each of these eleven different gossip strategies. Let me overview them, and give brief descriptions of what they stand for:

From the eleven different kinds of gossip, Gilmore (1978) derives four important features to classify gossip. First the different kinds of gossip can be classified according to the number of people taking part in the conversation. Gossip can occur in small groups, or in larger social settings. Second, the status of the gossiped subject divides all kinds of gossip in two groups; either the gossiped subjects are of the same social status of the gossipers, or the gossiped subject has a higher social status than the gossipers. Gilmore (1978) never heard any gossip about subjects who were lower social status than the gossipers. Third, the instrumentality of the gossip sender differs for gossip with clear intentions to reach the gossiped subject and more innocent gossip, lacking this clear intent to reach the gossipee. Fourth and lastly, gossip can be either legitimated or not. Only the most cruel kind of gossip, that which breaks up friendships, is not legitimated in this Spanish rural community.

 

Although Gilmore’s (1978) classification is useful to clarify research on gossip, I think it is not the best way to classify gossip. I think that a classification based on the different effects and functions of gossip might be better, then classifying on structural features. In the next two chapters, I will propose a way to construct a classification system of gossip funded on an operational and functional analysis.

 

 

5 Conclusion: a very general definition of gossip

 

To conclude this chapter, I resume the separate conclusions that follow from the critical overview on the different debates about what gossip is and is not, both as a noun and as an action. I end this chapter with giving a general definition of gossip, to frame my operational and functional analyses in. Again, I stress that this overall definition might be too general to use for research and might better be seen as an overall noun for different sub categorizations.

 

5.1 Resuming gossip as a noun

 

In summary, gossip as a noun is about human subjects. We do not gossip about non-human things, such as animals, events, etc. About these human subjects we gossip about a broad range of topics; all traits and behaviors of a certain person can become gossip topics.

 

All humans can be gossipees. We can gossip about living persons and dead persons, known persons, celebrities, and even unknown persons. However, we do not gossip about ourselves. Talking about yourself, which is called self-disclosure, might be very similar to gossip, but gossip is restricted to talk about a third person. The gossipee can be present in the conversation. However the gossipee is never the sender or direct receiver of gossip about him or herself. He or she can be physically present when two or more other person’s gossip about him or her, but then the gossip is not directed straight to the gossipee, but to other participants of the conversation.

 

Gossip is most commonly linked to bad talk, but also covers innocent talk and even good talk. Through gossip we can both disgrace and appraise others. And, gossip can both be true and untrue. The sender himself or herself should have true/false knowledge about the information in order to label it as gossip. However, the receiver can be in doubt. Since gossip also embody lies, hearing the same piece of gossip multiple times can still be interesting for a receiver. Gossip is not only new information, it can be old news in the sense that what is being gossiped about happened in the past. It can also be old information in the sense that the receiver already heard this piece of gossip from someone else. The gossip then does not have news value, but credibility value.

 

5.2 Resuming gossip as an action

 

Everyone gossips. Gossip occurs in every society, among young and old people. You can gossip with just a few people or with a lot, depending on the medium you use to transmit your information.

 

Gossip is transmitted through different channels. Oral conversations, face-to-face settings, are the oldest form of gossip and still constitute the major part of out gossip transactions, but nowadays gossip is also transmitted through newer channels, such as media channels.

 

Focusing on the relation between those gossiping I did not make any restrictions. Anyone can potentially gossip with anyone else. Although some exclude professional conversations, such as doctors discussing their patients, from gossip, I opt not to do this. Two doctors use gossip in a functional way, just as two neighbors use gossip to discuss what is going on in their social environment. This will become clearer in chapter 4, where I attribute different functions to gossip.

 

Lastly, gossip affects the receiver, often eliciting feelings of surprise. If the receiver is not surprised by the content, then this content should at least embody some deviance. The gossipee must have a trait or must have acted different from what any average person has or does. However, even though gossip is motivated talk, the intentions of the gossip sender do not have to be consciously present.

 

5.3 Gossip in the most general sense

 

“A minimal working definition of gossip seems to be ‘the informal and private transmission of information about one or more persons between two or more other persons.” (Hannerz, 1967: 36). Hannerz’s definition is close to what I suggest to be a good working definition for gossip, but lacks some of the critical restrictions, such as contextual and goal constraints. Taking notice of all critical points of discussion about gossip, I propose to define gossip in the most general sense as:

 

Gossip is information about the deviant or surprising (which both depend on the context) traits and behaviors of one (or more) third person(s) (most often non-present, but potentially present in the conversation), and where the sender has true/false knowledge of the gossip content.

 

This most general definition is useful to perform an effect-study and functional analysis of gossip, to better understand the uses and functions of this form of human conversation. However, to conduct research on gossip more specific definitions are required. In the next chapters I present my effect-study and functional analysis, from which I derive the more specific sub definitions that can be used for empirical research.

 

home list theses contence previous next